The Curious Case of the Christian Baker – A Summary of Oral Arguments

Image

This article is a short summary of the oral arguments in Masterpiece Cakeshop, Ltd. v. Colorado Civil Rights Commission, which was argued before the U.S. Supreme Court on December 5, 2017. In the article, I provide a few bits of commentary. But, this is primarily a summary.1 Hopefully, it can spur each of us on to consider the issue of soul liberty in the public square in these troubled times.

Baker’s Response

Kristen Waggoner, Philipps’ attorney, argued his objection is not to the people who want the cake. Instead, the objection is the message it communicates. “The First Amendment prohibits the government from forcing people to express messages that their violate religious convictions” (4:12-19). The back and forth centered on this point. What is “speech?” How do you separate the identity of the customer from the message the product communicates?

Ginsburg opened by asking about off the shelf products: would Philipps provide these to a same-sex couple (4:21-5:4; 10:9-19)? Absolutely, Waggoner said, a pre-made item wasn’t compelled speech (5:5-8). The crux of the issue is intent. When Phillips puts a pre-made product on display “in the stream of commerce in a public accommodation setting, his speech has been completed” (6:1-4). However, when you consider custom designed cakes, it’s a whole new ballgame (6:7-10). Thus it is with Phillips: “we are drawing the line prior to the compulsion — there can be no compulsion of speech” (6:4-6). And, this is about more than putting “words and symbols” onto the cake – it’s the act of custom making the product itself (8:8-19).

So, where is the line? Who can claim an artistic exemption on the basis of compelled speech? The justices hammered away on this line. Can a florist (11:9-13)? Yes, Waggoner said (11:14-17). What about a wedding invitation designer (11:18-21)? Of course (11:22). What about hair stylists (12:8) or makeup artists (12:17)?

  • “Absolutely not,” Waggoner says (12:9).
  • Justice Kagan is aghast; “Why is there no speech in — in creating a wonderful hairdo” (12:12-13)?

Waggoner provided a legal answer, but not a particularly logical one. A tailor, a chef, a hairstylist and a makeup artist don’t produce “speech” because they (1) aren’t communicating a message with their product, and (2) their product isn’t analogous to other forms of protected speech (12:9-11; 12:23-13:5; 14:16-21).

This prompted Justice Sotomayor to ask how the Court could protect Phillips’ cake as a medium for public expression when its primary purpose is to be eaten (15:21-25)!? Simple, Waggoner replied.

“[I]in the wedding context, Mr. Phillips is painting on a blank canvas. He is creating a painting on that canvas that expresses messages, and including words and symbols in those messages.” (16:9-14).

Well, what about sandwich artists (16:24-17:3)? The difference, Waggoner says, is the message being conveyed:

… when we have someone that is sketching and sculpting and hand designing something, that is creating a temporary sculpture that serves as the centerpiece of what they believe to be a religious wedding celebration, that cake expresses a message (17:4-10).

This distinction is the heart of the issue, according to Waggoner. If the very nature of the product is communicative, then you have “speech,” and this speech cannot be compelled. For example, this is why architecture is not “speech,” because “buildings are functional, not communicative” (17:20-23).

Justice Breyer weighed in:

So, in other words, Mies or Michelangelo or someone is not protected when he creates the Laurentian steps, but this cake baker is protected when he creates the cake without any message on it for a wedding? Now, that - that really does baffle me, I have to say (18:4-10).

So, where on earth is the line (19:1-11)? What should we do? The answer, Waggoner says, is simple: “Is the individual who’s being compelled to speak objecting to the message that’s contained in that speech or the person? And that’s usually a very obvious inquiry” (20:7-11). This is why Waggoner believes the issue of public accommodation laws related to race are completely different: “we know that that objection would be based to who the person is, rather than what the message is” (23:3-6).

Here is the dividing line, and it isn’t something a secular Court can decide. Is sexual identity a legitimate category at all, from a Christian perspective? You can’t set theology aside here, because it informs how you answer the question. Everybody has a foundation for his worldview, and the Christian worldview (based on the Scriptures) proclaims that all sexual thoughts, intents and actions outside a monogamous, male and female sexual relationship in the context of a marriage covenant is deviant. To the Christian, “sexual identity” is not a legitimate category, because it isn’t part of the original, “good” created order. Race is, sexual identity is not.2

Waggoner, of course, didn’t go there. She simply continued to push the distinction between the racial public accommodation laws (which were about who the person is) and the Phillips case which, she insisted, is about the message, not the people. It’s unclear whether she (and her client) actually believe this, or if it’s merely a convenient legal peg to hang their case on.

How can the State fairly decide whether this message vs. identity distinction isn’t just a smokescreen? This was Justice Gorsuch’s question (24:18-21), and he didn’t receive a satisfactory answer.

Solicitor General’s Response on Behalf of Baker

The Solicitor General, Noel Francisco, insisted there must be “breathing space” for free speech protections for business owners, so they aren’t compelled to engage in “speech” for an event they disagree with (26:1-8). Dignity interests cut both ways, he argued (28:1-8).

What about a situation in a rural context, where only very limited services are available (28:10-29:11)? Leave that to the individual states, Francisco said (29:12-17).

Where is “the line?” You figure that out, he answered, by applying a two-fold test:

  1. Can the “art” in question be analogized to traditional art in a legitimate way, and
  2. “is it predominantly art or predominantly utilitarian” (41:1-3)?

In Phillips’ case, Francisco observed, “people pay very high prices for these highly sculpted cakes, not because they taste good, but because of their artistic qualities” (41:3-6).

The goal is the intent of the purchaser. Is it merely a cake to be eaten? Why not go to Safeway? No, they clearly sought out Phillips so he could create, sculpt and fashion a special cake which is analogous to a traditional sculpture “except for the medium used,” (40:18-20). Is the creation’s purpose and effect intended to be (1) artistic, or (2) utilitarian? That is the key to answering the question (42:2-24).

In Phillips’ case, they sought him out for artistic purposes, to create an artistic and aesthetic effect on the wedding guests. Thus, they asked him to “speak” through the medium of the cake, and his “speech” must be protected. Francisco closed with a “slippery-slope” argument:

… if you were to disagree with our basic principle, putting aside the line about whether a cake falls on speech or nonspeech side of the line, you really are envisioning a situation in which you could force, for example, a gay opera singer to perform at the Westboro Baptist Church just because that opera singer would be willing to perform at the National Cathedral (46:13-21).

Response from State of Colorado

Frederick Yarger, the Solicitor General for Colorado, presented a simple argument (47:12-22):

  1. if you are a retail establishment, then
  2. you’re subject to anti-discrimination laws, and
  3. “you cannot turn away from your storefront if you’re a retail store” (65:21-23).

It really is that simple and, if you’re a retail establishment, the State can require you to serve a customer (50:11-19).

What about, say, a same-sex couple who went to Catholic Legal Services and demanded to be given legal service related to their marriage? Would Colorado force them to provide service (50:21-51:23)? Yes, Yarger says, if Catholic Legal Services were operating in a retail context, “then Colorado would have the ability to regulate them” (52:3).

Justice Kennedy brought up an interesting point. Colorado’s opinion read, in part, that “freedom of religion used to justify discrimination is a despicable piece of rhetoric” (52:14-16). Why shouldn’t the Court assume Colorado is prejudiced against religion, and act accordingly? Kennedy asked Yarger three times if he disavowed the statement, and Yarger tap-danced mightily to avoid answering (52:17-53:15). If there were a bias on Colorado’s part, he claimed, of course there would be the problem (54:12-16). But, such was not the case (55:15-23).

Colorado’s issue, Yarger said, is that Philipps’ actions were based on the identity of the customer. Phillips may claim the message is the problem but, Yarger argued, the message here is linked with the customer’s identity, so the argument lacks merit. “[T]he message in this case, Your Honor, depended entirely on the identity of the customer who was ordering the cake” (62:15-18). So, if the baker chooses to refuse service, he is being discriminatory (63:16-21).

Justice Kennedy, once again, chimed in with some stern words (64:3-8):

Counselor, tolerance is essential in a free society. And tolerance is most meaningful when it’s mutual. It seems to me that the state in its position here has been neither tolerant nor respectful of Mr. Phillips’s religious beliefs.

Yarger disagreed, and his position hinges on granting the idea that “sexual identity” is a valid category, on par with race and sex (64:14-65:3). They’re protected by public accommodation laws, so “sexual identity” must be, too.

Response from Homosexual Couple

Their attorney, David Cole, traveled over much of the same ground Yarger did. Beware the slippery slope: “to accept his argument leads to unacceptable consequences” (74:20-21). Sexual identity is a valid category, along with race and sex (75:9-16).

Cole dismissed Francisco’s “artistic purpose and effect” argument. If a mom buys a cake for a child’s birthday party, “no one thinks that the baker is wishing happy birthday to the four-year-old. It’s the mom” (78:1-3). The issue isn’t some alleged “message,” it’s the identity of the homosexual couple. “Because in this case, again, the only thing the baker knew about these customers was that they were gay. And, as a result, he refused to sell them any wedding cake” (79:4-8).

For Colorado, if you’re in retail, your private beliefs do not allow you to discriminate against a protected class (92:6-10), and sexual identity is a protected class (87:13-19; 89:7-10). Justice Kennedy retorted, “your identity thing is just too facile” (89:23-24).

Conclusion

The legal arguments hinge on whether the act of making a cake is “speech,” and whether that speech can be compelled by the State. Both sides presented valid slippery-slope arguments in support of their own positions. On balance, it is doubtful whether you can logically separate the identity of a homosexual couple from the message their wedding cake is meant to convey.

Aside from the legal arguments, there is a more profound question for the Christian – where is the dividing line between one’s right to soul liberty, and the opportunity to share the Gospel in all sorts of negative contexts? Could Philipps have baked the cake, and still made a positive opportunity out of this? Have his actions served to “maintain good conduct among the Gentiles, so that in case they speak against you as wrongdoers, they may see your good deeds and glorify God on the day of visitation” (1 Pet 2:12)?

Should we allow everyone do what they want, according to their own consciences? Is this the best solution? Os Guinness wrote a book advocating a sophisticated version of this approach, and remarked,

Soul freedom for all was once attacked as naive and utopian, and it is still resisted as subversive. Yet it is not only a shining ideal but a dire necessity today and an eminently practical solution to the predicaments of our time. Truly it is the golden key to a troublesome situation in which the darker angels must not be allowed to dominate.”3

But, when it gets down to brass tacks, how do we actually do this? This case is about that question. How do you allow people to express their sincere beliefs, yet crack down on genuine bigotry and hatred? How do you carve out these exceptions, and where does it end? In a moment of candor, Justice Breyer admitted, “I can’t think of a way to do it” (59:11-12).

Notes

1 I make no attempt to summarize or even reference the various briefs filed by the Petitioners or Respondents. Here is the question before the Supreme Court. If you’re interested, you can find them. Throughout this article, I’m referencing the official transcript of oral arguments. The citation format in the article is page number:line number.

2 Of course, in the end, the only category distinctions which have eternal significance are (1) believer or (2) non-believer. Or, as the Didache puts it, “there are two ways, one of life and one of death, and there is a great difference between the two ways” (Didache 1:1).

3 Os Guinness, The Global Public Square: Religious Freedom and the Making of a World Safe for Diversity (Downer’s Grove, IL: IVP, 2013), 14.

Discussion

Much appreciate the summary, Tyler.

Statements like these from the Colorado tram are factually incorrect:

“Because in this case, again, the only thing the baker knew about these customers was that they were gay. And, as a result, he refused to sell them any wedding cake” (79:4-8)

I know some on the court will see through this, hopefully a majority.

Tomorrow: why Masterpiece deserves to win this case. If a ruling comes out today, it’ll be “why they deserved to win.”

Views expressed are always my own and not my employer's, my church's, my family's, my neighbors', or my pets'. The house plants have authorized me to speak for them, however, and they always agree with me.

Really, the state of Colorado’s case, taken to its full extent, would compel a Jewish baker to make a cake for Adolf Hitler’s birthday. It is our country’s shame that courts at any level have fallen for this.

Aspiring to be a stick in the mud.

What do you think of the legal arguments? Which side presented a more compelling argument? Kennedy is the swing vote, and he’s clearly on the baker’s side.

This is the key:

  • Can you separate the identity of the homosexual customers from the message they intended the cake to convey? Set aside the legal rationale; do think this is logically possible? Do you buy that this distinction is legitimate?
  • Is sexual identity is on par with other public accommodation laws (e.g. race and sex, etc.)?

That’s the whole ball game. This is a secular Court and, to be honest, I haven’t the foggiest idea what they ought to do and how they should rule. I don’t think they know, either.

Tyler is a pastor in Olympia, WA and works in State government.

The oral arguments aren’t really the meat and potatoes of the testimony, or so I’m told. The bulk of the case is in legal briefs and the arguments try to clarify issues the Justices want to know more about, etc. In many of their comments/questions the Justices seem to be only confirming their understanding of points they’ve already read on one side or the other.

I personally don’t think there is any real difficulty separating the message from the identity… or, more accurately, I don’t think there is really anything to separate in this case because the link between the identity and the event is real but not relevant. The question is whether the state can force a person to approve of behaviors that are specific to an identity. It’s the unfortunate expansion of the identity concept and adding behavior-based protected classes that has gotten us into this mess. With race, gender, and age, there are no behaviors that are unique to the identity. With religion and sexual identity there are. But we don’t have any tradition, as far as I know, of requiring sellers of creative work to sell items that express approval of someone’s religion. We’ve not expected that. Yet now, per ACLU et al., we’re supposed to do that with sexual identity.

It should not stand. Whether it will is anybody’s guess.

But I think this is partly what one of the Justices was referring to when he characterized the identity concept in Colorado’s case as “too facile.”

Edit: I lumped religion in with sexual identity above, but really one’s religious beliefs are not inseparably linked to “identity” either. This is a new thing, trying to claim that a behavior or concept (in this case, a gay wedding) is so much a part of an identity that rejecting the behavior or concept is “discrimination.”

Can’t see how it could stand.

Views expressed are always my own and not my employer's, my church's, my family's, my neighbors', or my pets'. The house plants have authorized me to speak for them, however, and they always agree with me.

Agreed that the oral arguments are simply an opportunity for the justices to ask questions based on the briefs filed by each party. But, in that respect, it’s a very interesting opportunity to see those legal arguments brought out of the ivory tower and subject to actual questioning. In some ways, they’re more helpful than the actual briefs.

Tyler is a pastor in Olympia, WA and works in State government.

…are about the same as Aaron’s expressed in the other thread. Freedom of religion is in the Constitution explicitly, whereas the “right” of homosexuals to marry is a tenuous interpretation of the 14th Amendment. Hence ordinarily the right to freedom of religion and expression ought to be honored unless there is a BIG legal deal—hurting someone’s feelings doesn’t rise to that.

Regarding the status of the arguments, Tyler’s take is about the same as mine with Aaron’s caveat; sometimes the Supremes surprise us with decisions after promising looking oral hearings. I think that was the case with the cases that affirmed Obamacare, really. I notice as well that one of my “go to” references, Powerlineblog.com, is quiet so far. Hence I think there’s a very real possibility that somebody’s working hard on Anthony Kennedy to help Sotomayor, Kagan, Ginsberg, and Breyer write freedom of religion out of the 1st Amendment.

Aspiring to be a stick in the mud.

On oral arguments, agree that there is value in them. They’re important to give the public some access to their deliberations, but also sometimes ideas framed in legalese on paper sound sensible until confronted about them out loud… then they sound ridiculous. The out loud impression isn’t always the “right” one, but it’s a different perspective and that’s healthy, I think.

As for freedom of religion, I don’t really see this as a freedom of religion case. It has pretty huge implications for freedom of religion, probably, but, if the Court rules for Colorado, it’s basically saying that the state can require you to express approval of things you disapprove of. It wouldn’t be a blanket empowerment of the state to do that, but it would be a step toward the end of free speech — because the case doesn’t specify that the belief you’re required to support is against your religion; it’s just against what you believe to be true and right. It’s mostly a secular case, they way they’ve argued it … at least based on what I’ve seen from ADF and the oral arguments.

Views expressed are always my own and not my employer's, my church's, my family's, my neighbors', or my pets'. The house plants have authorized me to speak for them, however, and they always agree with me.